The American Psychiatric Association (APA) has updated its Privacy Policy and Terms of Use, including with new information specifically addressed to individuals in the European Economic Area. As described in the Privacy Policy and Terms of Use, this website utilizes cookies, including for the purpose of offering an optimal online experience and services tailored to your preferences.

Please read the entire Privacy Policy and Terms of Use. By closing this message, browsing this website, continuing the navigation, or otherwise continuing to use the APA's websites, you confirm that you understand and accept the terms of the Privacy Policy and Terms of Use, including the utilization of cookies.

×
Open ForumFull Access

Preventing the Unpredicted: Managing Violence Risk in Mental Health Care

Published Online:

Experts in violence risk management are lately grappling, like climatologists, with inconvenient truths: that mental health professionals cannot predict an individual's violent behavior much better than chance ( 1 , 2 ); that clinicians could do a better job of predicting violence if they would use the tools developed by risk experts ( 3 )—but they don't; and that even if clinicians could accurately forecast violence, there is not much they can do about it. Competent patients often decline or stop treatment, which is their right, and the remedies for mental illness are not designed to prevent much of what causes violence anyway ( 4 , 5 ).

Nevertheless, whenever a person with serious mental illness commits a rare act of horrific violence in the community, two allegations surface: that mental health professionals should have seen this coming and that they should have prevented it ( 6 , 7 , 8 ). What is an expert to do?

Prediction versus prevention

The Virginia Tech Review Panel, in its report on the tragic shooting in Blacksburg last year, cited the campus mental health care team as "ineffective in connecting the dots or heeding the red flags that were so apparent with Cho" ( 6 ). The report asserted that "there are particular behaviors and indicators of dangerous mental instability that threat assessment professionals have documented among murderers" and that in Cho's case the professionals either did not see these warning signs or ignored them.

For clinicians so accused, the truth ceases to be inconvenient. Refuge is sought in the skillful defenses of ignorance, ineffectiveness, and irrelevance ( 9 , 10 , 11 ). "We can't predict violence in individual patients," they say, "so how can we prevent the unpredictable? And we can't cure major causes of violence anyway (poverty and past trauma, for example), so what good is prediction?"

There is a kernel of truth under this cover. After all, what doctors are supposed to do mainly is treat diseases and their symptoms. Psychiatrists are not psychics, and they are not the police.

However, the defense falls short when it conflates prediction and prevention ( 12 , 13 ). That these are two different things—not necessarily related—becomes obvious when one thinks of other areas of medicine. A primary care physician cannot predict which individual patient will have a heart attack or get cancer but is rightfully expected to do something to prevent early deaths from these diseases across a panel of patients: screen for risk factors and early signs of disease, work with patients to reduce modifiable risk factors, and intervene promptly when worrisome signs of pathology are detected ( 14 ).

There is also the "bad weather" example: pretty good predictability of totally unpreventable events. However, although we can't prevent hurricanes, we can surely take steps to limit a storm's damage to us ( 15 ). We pay attention when the Big One is coming, warn everyone in its path, and then load up the dogs and evacuate.

Of course, the argument about violence is that we don't know when the storm is approaching. But maybe it is not such a good idea to be living on a sinking sandbar in the first place. We have large numbers of people with severe mental illness living in jails, homeless shelters, and substandard apartments in impoverished neighborhoods where every block has two liquor stores and a pawn shop. Then we talk about preventing violence by tweaking antipsychotic treatment regimens ( 4 , 16 ).

There is much that both public policy makers and mental health professionals could do to limit the human catastrophes for which they are sometimes, rightly or wrongly, held responsible. To be clear: clinicians actually can predict violence with reasonable certainty—they just need to consider their patients as a group, the way a public-health epidemiologist would ( 9 , 14 ). A clinical team treating 100 persons with schizophrenia in the community could confidently predict that a small proportion—more than one and fewer than ten (or so)—will engage in some serious violent behavior within the coming six months ( 17 ). An additional ten to 15 (or so) will engage in minor acts of violence toward others, such as hitting someone without causing physical injury. The clinicians could count on it.

The treatment team could go further and confidently expect that these violent acts will occur more frequently among subsets of their patients who have certain characteristics: young adults with severe mental illness who have trauma and violence in their past, substance abuse in their present, and no plans for taking prescribed psychotropic medications in their future ( 4 , 16 , 18 ). Knowing that some of these patients are going to be violent—that it is not a matter of "if" but "when"—means that mental health professionals are responsible for taking whatever steps they can, within reason, to prepare for violence and thus limit its damage and reach ( 2 , 12 , 19 ).

Interventions and leverage

And what can mental health professionals do? There is the timeworn strategy of containment: put a solid barrier between the source of harm and potential victims ( 13 ). (This is what the U.S. Army Corps of Engineers had in mind when they built the levees in New Orleans, which worked well for a long time.) The problem is that some ways of limiting risk are highly effective but morally illegitimate. Before the 1960s countless potential acts of violence by people with mental illness were probably thwarted by keeping patients locked up in psychiatric hospitals for decades and giving them major tranquilizers. A half-century later, clinicians have come to regard inpatient civil commitment sensibly, the way many people view abortion: it should be safe, legal, and rare.

Community-based "leverage," on the other hand, is not so rare. Use of the mere threat of hospitalization or jail or of withholding housing or money to ensure adherence with outpatient mental health treatment has become common practice ( 20 ). Is this coercive? Perhaps so, although research suggests that most patients with severe mental illness do not perceive it to be ( 21 ). Some patients clearly do feel coerced but mainly when they are subjected to more than one form of leverage at a time—such as having a judge order treatment and having a representative money manager who believes in rewarding the patient—with the patient's own money—for taking medications ( 22 ). Stack the "leverages" on top of each other, and they start to feel heavy.

Does the use of community leverage prevent violence by people with severe mental illness? It can, but not necessarily. Legally mandating services will do nothing (at least nothing good) if the services being mandated are unavailable or ineffective ( 23 ). Even if we assume that treatment can sometimes work ( 16 ), it needs to target actual risk factors for violence, at least indirectly, in order to prevent violence. The risk factors have to be modifiable by something that mental health professionals can reasonably do. And the clinicians need to know that the risk factors exist in the first place.

The challenge of risk assessment

Apropos of knowing, why don't professionals routinely and systematically assess, document, and monitor dynamic risk factors for violence, as some experts have lately recommended ( 19 , 24 )? Why not do this at least for patients above a baseline threshold of putative risk, such as those with a previous history of violence or threats or with a history of substance abuse? Given the potential for catastrophe, would it not be better to find out those "known unknowns" (as a famous war poet once put it)?

Maybe not. For one thing, the notion of routine violence risk assessment—built into the machinery of usual care—rests on a besmirching assumption about all of the people seeking mental health services ( 25 , 26 ). For another thing, who is this for? Screening for medical conditions is primarily to benefit the patient. Screening for violence risk is primarily to benefit other people. This difference raises nettlesome ethical questions. Should the patient get to choose whether or not to be screened for violent behavior, given that the interests of others may be at stake? Who gets to decide what to do, or not to do, with the resulting information (such as deciding not to act on a positive finding, for example)? And what happens if the information is simply wrong?

Structured risk assessment is not that sharp and discriminating. It's not like looking for a 10-mm polyp in a colon—the best endoscopists likely won't miss it if it's there and won't find it if it's not ( 27 ). Rather, assessing patients' violence potential often involves a perverse tradeoff between unacceptably high rates of false negatives and false positives ( 28 ). The Violence Risk Appraisal Guide is perhaps the most accurate tool yet devised to assess risk. It has a sensitivity of 73% and a specificity of 63% ( 29 ), substantially below what would be considered acceptable in medicine for a screening instrument. Chest X-rays are not used to screen for lung cancer, because the sensitivity and specificity of the procedure when used in this way are only 84% and 90% ( 30 ).

Then there is the business-model problem. Structured risk assessment is not reimbursed by insurance the way medical tests are, where doctors can make almost as much money doing screening procedures as they could be sued for if they did not ( 31 , 32 ).

Nevertheless, maybe there is a lesson or two to be learned from the way medicine manages the risk of a disease that you probably won't get but that might kill you if you do. If medical professionals tell us to get screened for it, we don't complain; we show up and assume the position. Should prevention fail, we get treatment fast. Should treatment ultimately fail, our family members will not sue the doctor for failing to predict and prevent our demise. They will invite him to our funeral, grateful that "he did everything he could." And the doctor will remember us fondly as he silently thanks us for getting that colonoscopy.

Lamentably, violence risk appraisal and management in mental health practice are not there yet. We need more accurate and efficient prediction tools, particularly for use in nonforensic patient populations. We also need better incentives for practitioners to use them and for payers to reimburse for their use (for example, through pay-for-performance policies.) If we do reach a point where it is possible, and feasible, to predict individual patient violence with a high degree of precision, we need better interventions—more effective and tolerable, less coercive and stigmatizing—to forestall the violence that we are predicting, and we need more choices in community care than that between a pill and a shot.

In the meantime, clinicians should, of course, do the best they can with the tools and resources that are available to them. Let not the perfect defeat the good (or the better than nothing.) Don't screen every patient, but for those who have committed violent acts in the past or report thoughts of hurting someone in the future, a structured risk assessment should be, and is becoming, the standard of care ( 3 ).

Conclusions

It hardly needs saying that all patients with serious mental illnesses—not just those at risk of violence—could benefit from accurate assessment of their problems, timely services that include evidence-based interventions, diligent clinical follow-up, and appropriate outreach to those who cannot or will not voluntarily seek the treatment they need. Clearly, there are complex economic, legal, and other systemic reasons why all psychiatric patients currently do not get the best treatment that clinicians already know how to provide. But if they did, it is likely that much patient violence—and a great deal of human heartache all around—would be averted in the process.

And the risk experts? Perhaps they should step back and consider the field that they are in. In the end, a career is not all about what one knows but about what good one can do and the value people place on it. The median salary of gastroenterologists in the United States is over 175% of the median salary of psychiatrists; maybe there's some reason for that. On the other hand, psychiatrists make about twice as much as meteorologists ( 33 ).

Acknowledgments and disclosures

Preparation of this article was supported by the National Institute of Mental Health through an Independent Research Career Award (K02-MH67864) to the author. The author acknowledges the helpful comments of several colleagues who read a draft of the article: Paul Appelbaum, M.D., Wendell Bell, Ph.D., Alec Buchanan, Ph.D., M.D., Thomas B. Cole, M.D., Eric Elbogen, PhD., Kai Erikson, Ph.D., John Monahan, Ph.D., and Marvin Swartz, M.D.

The author reports no competing interests.

Dr. Swanson is affiliated with the Department of Psychiatry and Behavioral Sciences, Duke University School of Medicine, DUMC 3071, Durham, NC 27710 (e-mail: [email protected]).

References

1. Lidz CW, Mulvey EP, Gardner W: The accuracy of predictions of violence to others. JAMA 269:1007–1011, 1993Google Scholar

2. Monahan J: A jurisprudence of risk assessment: forecasting harm among prisoners, predators, and patients. Virginia Law Review 92:391–434, 1993Google Scholar

3. Lamberg L: New tools aid violence risk assessment (reprinted). JAMA 298:499–501, 2007Google Scholar

4. Swanson JW, Swartz MS, Essock SM, et al: The social-environmental context of violent behavior in persons treated for severe mental illness. American Journal of Public Health 92:1523–1531, 2002Google Scholar

5. Swanson JW, Van Dorn RA, Swartz MS: Alternative pathways to violence in persons with schizophrenia: the role of childhood antisocial behavior problems. Law and Human Behavior, 2007. DOI 10.1007/s10979-007-9095-7Google Scholar

6. Virginia Tech Review Panel: Mass Shootings at Virginia Tech: April 16, 2007: Report of the Review Panel, Aug 2007. Richmond, Va, Office of the Governor. Available at www.governor.virginia.govGoogle Scholar

7. LeBourgeois HW III, Pinals DA, Williams V, et al: Hindsight bias among psychiatrists. Journal of the American Academy of Psychiatry and the Law 35:67–73, 2007Google Scholar

8. Munro E, Rumgay J: Role of risk assessment in reducing homicides by people with mental illness. British Journal of Psychiatry 176:116–120, 2000Google Scholar

9. Hart SD, Michie C, Cooke DJ: Precision of actuarial risk assessment instruments: evaluating the "margins of error" of group v individual predictions of violence. British Journal of Psychiatry 190(suppl 49):S60–S65, 2007Google Scholar

10. Slobogin C: Proving the Unprovable: The Role of Science, Law, and Speculation in Adjudicating Incompetence and Dangerousness. New York, Oxford University Press, 2006Google Scholar

11. Grisso T, Appelbaum PS: Is it unethical to offer predictions of future violence? Law and Human Behavior 16:621–633, 1992Google Scholar

12. Heilbrun K: Prediction versus management models relevant to risk assessment: the importance of legal decision-making context. Law and Human Behavior 21:347–359, 1997Google Scholar

13. Haddon W Jr: The basic strategies for reducing damage from hazards of all kinds. Hazard Prevention 16:8–12, 1980Google Scholar

14. Rose G: Sick individuals and sick populations. International Journal of Epidemiology 30:427–432, 2001Google Scholar

15. Riad JK, Norris FH, Ruback B: Predicting evacuation in two major disasters: risk perception, social influence, and access to resources. Journal of Applied Social Psychology 29:918–934, 1999Google Scholar

16. Swanson JW, Swartz MS, Elbogen E: Effectiveness of atypical antipsychotic medications in reducing violent behavior among persons with schizophrenia in community-based treatment. Schizophrenia Bulletin 30:3–20, 2004Google Scholar

17. Swanson JW, Swartz MS, Van Dorn RA, et al: A national study of violent behavior in persons with schizophrenia. Archives of General Psychiatry 63:490–499, 2006Google Scholar

18. Swartz MS, Swanson JW, Hiday VA, et al: Violence and severe mental illness: the effects of substance abuse and nonadherence to medications. American Journal of Psychiatry 155:226–231, 1998Google Scholar

19. Appelbaum PS, Gutheil TG: Clinical Handbook of Psychiatry and the Law, 4th ed. Hagerstown, Md, Wolters Kluwer/Lippincott, Williams and Wilkins, 2007Google Scholar

20. Monahan J, Redlich A, Swanson J, et al: Use of leverage to improve adherence to psychiatric treatment in the community. Psychiatric Services 56:37–44, 2005Google Scholar

21. Swartz MS, Swanson JW, Kim M, et al: Use of involuntary outpatient commitment or related civil court treatment orders in five United States communities. Psychiatric Services 57:343–349, 2006Google Scholar

22. Elbogen EB, Swanson JW, Swartz MS: Mandated community treatment, representative payeeship, perceived coercion, and treatment adherence. Journal of Nervous and Mental Disease 191:629–637, 2003Google Scholar

23. Swanson JW, Swartz MS, Borum RB, et al: Involuntary out-patient commitment and reduction of violent behaviour in persons with severe mental illness. British Journal of Psychiatry 176:324–331, 2000Google Scholar

24. Mullen P: Schizophrenia and violence: from correlations to preventive strategies. Advances in Psychiatric Treatment 12:239–248, 2006Google Scholar

25. Pescosolido BA, Monahan J, Link BG, et al: The public's view of the competence, dangerousness, and need for legal coercion of persons with mental health problems. American Journal of Public Health 89:1339–1345, 1999Google Scholar

26. Van Dorn RA, Swanson JW, Elbogen EB, et al.: A comparison of stigmatizing attitudes toward persons with schizophrenia in four stakeholder groups: perceived likelihood of violence and desire for social distance. Psychiatry 68:152–163, 2005Google Scholar

27. Van Rijn JC, Reitsma JB, Stoker J, et al: Polyp miss rate determined by tandem colonoscopy: a systematic review. American Journal of Gastroenterology 101:343–350, 2006Google Scholar

28. Gardner W, Lidz CW, Mulvey EP, et al: A comparison of actuarial methods for identifying repetitively violent patients with mental illnesses. Law and Human Behavior 20:35–48, 1996Google Scholar

29. Rice M, Harris G: Violent recidivism: assessing predictive validity. Journal of Consulting and Clinical Psychology 63:737–748, 1995Google Scholar

30. Gavelli G, Giampalma E: Sensitivity and specificity of chest x-ray screening for lung cancer. Cancer 89:2453–2456, 2000Google Scholar

31. Luchtefeld MA, Kim DG: Colonoscopy in the office setting is safe, and financially sound… for now. Diseases of the Colon and Rectum 49:377–382, 2006Google Scholar

32. Prajapati DN, Saeian K, Binion DG, et al: Volume and yield of screening colonoscopy at a tertiary medical center after change in Medicare reimbursement. American Journal of Gastroenterology 98:194–199, 2003Google Scholar

33. CNN Money.com: Salary Wizard. Available at salary.money.cnn.com. Accessed Dec 20, 2007Google Scholar